[This is one of twenty-one essays in the book Man and the Divine, published in August 2018. The book is available in ePub format from leading retailers of eBooks, such as Barnes & Noble, Blio, Kobo, Itunes, Inktera, Smashwords, etc. Information about Man and the Divine can be found here]
***
It is unclear that the realm of the divine
has reality. It is real, and at the same time it is not. The only argument for the world of existence
is that it is a poor copy of the divine world. And the divine world is
uncertain. So how ‘real’ is the world of existence? What is the way out of this
dilemma?
The answer is intentionality. The objective
world is subject to change, as is the understanding of men. We cannot know the
full properties of God, because, among other things, God is transcendent of
human understanding. How can mortal man then understand the properties and
nature of the divine, and how can the gods have a genuine involvement in the
world? The answer arrived at, it would seem, is that the human understanding
does not need to encompass the actual nature of the divine in order to have
commerce with it.
This is an exceptionally important point, since, beyond
legitimizing commerce with the divine despite the definition of God as beyond
human understanding, it also provides the intellectual basis for the creation of
multiple gods. Essentially therefore the idea of isolating the properties of
God, insofar as they can be understood, was understood to be a way of accessing
the nature of these properties, and therefore to allow operations to take
place, establishing a commerce between the divine and the world of change.
Intentionality explains why the ancients
created a multiplicity of gods. If the divine itself cannot by definition be
completely defined and understood, at least certain properties and attributes
can be understood. These can therefore be defined and named as ways of
accessing the divine. This does not at all conflict with the idea that the
reality of the divine is in question. Instead this view argues that there is in
fact a subjective component in the reality of the divine, at least insofar as
it is possible for us to have commerce with it. That is to say, some aspects of
the divine are accessible to the human mind. We cannot prove that it is real or
that it exists in any sense, but despite this uncertainty, there are certain
properties of the divine which are indisputable. Proof of the whole nature of
the divine is unimportant, since this cannot, by the definition of the divine,
be demonstrated.. We might then say that all connection with the divine therefore
is an act of faith rather than certainty. The nature and power of the divine
can be understood, defined, invoked and accessed by man.
Viewed in this way, we can see that each of
the gods we encounter in ancient accounts represents a slice through the nature
of divinity, so that one god has a special interest in one thing as opposed to
another, a special set of characteristics or attributes, which more directly
can be understood than an abstract and indefinable numinous concept of
divinity. However the underlying numinous concept, in fact the objective numinous
reality itself, requires to be real and present as the ground of being behind
the multiplicity of gods.
This explains the phenomenon of henotheism, found in
ancient polytheism. Pharaoh, for example, as the incarnation of the the divine
on earth, could ‘appear’ as himself, or could appear in any appropriate form of
the divine. When smiting his enemies for example, he might appear as ‘Montu, in
his great form.’ He might be depicted on a temple wall as Montu, rather than in
the form of the king. It might also be the case that a divine pronouncement
might involve the speaker moving successively from the voice and vocabulary
associated with one god, to the mode of speech associated with another god, as
appropriate. This has been found in Assyrian records, where someone recorded in
a state of divine possession, speaks successively as the voice of different
gods.
Considered in this way, the divine world is
filled with a variety of gods. Some of these have been defined, and
subsequently invoked. Other aspects of the underlying divine reality have not
been defined or invoked, and remain as possibilities. In the world of
existence, the divinities which have been defined were given representation in
the form of images and statuary.
None of this should be taken to imply that
polytheism initially arose from such a complex and philosophically subtle
theory as this. We have much information about the growth of local pantheons in
the near east, and the way in which local gods were absorbed into state
pantheons, given increased importance over time, or diminished in importance,
according to requirements. They would be given family relationships which they
did not possess when they first arrived, and gain attributes and
characteristics which they did not have when they were first born in the
smaller urban centres.
We cannot easily know to what extent there was an
intellectual model behind the creation of polytheistic belief and worship from
its first appearance in the archaeological and textual record. It is likely
that much of what has been written about ancient polytheism from an
anthropological perspective is probably correct, and valuable to our
understanding. It is just that the account is incomplete from this limited
perspective, and anthropologists have hardly ever seriously considered the
possibility that some intellectual ideas might underpin the phenomenon as well.
Those notionally equipped to explore
this territory, the specialists in ancient philosophy and perhaps theologians,
have had many reasons to stay out of this territory. For them, the possibility
of the ancient presence of a sophisticated intellectual model, based on logical
argument, is not something which can be easily entertained. This is something
which belongs to the Greeks. Though the Greeks were polytheists, their
polytheism antedates the beginnings of philosophy in the historical record, and
therefore polytheism has no bearing on philosophy, or vice versa. Many writers
on both Greek religion and philosophy have found this arrangement to be
conveniently tidy and a boon to scholarship. But it is not the case.
Shortly before I began this work, Pope
Benedict visited the UK
in connection with the Beatification of Cardinal John Henry Newman. When I read
the details of the process of Beatification (essentially of making saints), I
was struck by the resemblance between the idea of this in the Catholic Church,
and the idea of setting up gods in antiquity (which will be explored in more
detail later on). The idea is that
someone has to request (in ancient parlance this would be to ‘invoke’) the
assistance of a person, now deceased, who showed especial virtues in life, and
has to receive a response to this request which amounts to a miracle.
This is worth unpicking in detail, in order
to understand the logic which is involved. It is not clear why someone would
invoke someone less than the divine itself, if the divine is on offer, unless
the virtues of a lesser being seem more appropriate. In other words, the
prospective saint offers what looks like a channel which is more likely to be
successful than the supplicant making a direct appeal to a God who is both difficult
to define, and to know.
The Catholic Church itself promotes the idea of
sainthood, and unambiguously points at likely candidates. Newman has been one
of those for quite sometime. Two miracles are required for the final elevation
to sainthood. Why miracles? Because miracles are defined as things which cannot
be accounted for in terms of earthly understanding. These may (in the extreme)
be things which defy our understanding of physics, but ordinarily are
occurrences such as unexpected remission from terminal illness, which ‘defies’
orthodox medical science. This was indeed the case for the supplicant who
invoked the assistance of John Henry Newman.
The argument therefore runs as follows:
Newman has special status in Heaven because an appeal for his assistance was
answered. Because the assistance defied earthly understanding and expectation,
the result was a miracle which otherwise could not have occurred. Therefore his
status in Heaven is proved*[1].
Thus it is that the Catholic Church sets up saints on earth, and also in
Heaven.
The Catholic Church is not based on
polytheistic belief. So it is
rather surprising to find that it supports the idea that divine intervention
can occur via the saints, rather than directly through the divine father, or
his incarnation on earth.
The only significant difference between the
Vatican ’s
idea of saints and the ancients idea of gods is that all of the saints are
supposed to have lived human lives before being elevated to a divine status in
Heaven. The ancients did not subject themselves to such an unreasonable
constraint, and created gods who had never lived, and who could never have
endured existence in the world. They could do this because they understood a formal
and technical mechanics underpinning connection between the earthly world of
existence, and divinity. The mechanics are still available to us in the
records.
It might be in order here to recap a little
on the nature of the intellectual model of reality which underpins polytheistic
belief, as we find it reflected in Greek texts, particularly those by Plato.
The most perfect entity it is possible for
man to conceive is God. God is reality itself. The world of existence as
understood by man is imperfect, and consists of imperfect representations of
reality. The world of appearance as understood by man is subject to change and
corruption, whereas the world of divine reality as conceived by man is eternal.
God is real. Existence is full of
representations, more or less false, more or less true. Reality and existence
are opposed. Man can apprehend that this is the case.
Since existence is suspended from reality,
as a poor image of it, it is subject to change. Since man is an existent
creature, man’s perception of reality is also subject to change. Both the
nature of things which are existent, and man’s perception of these changeable
things, are perpetually in flux.
Man cannot have full understanding of the
nature of the divine, since, by definition, the divine transcends the world of
sensible reality, and existence. It is in essence transcendental, and to the
fullest extent.
However there are a number of ways in which
the world of existence can access the divine reality. Several characteristic
features of the divine remain in the sensible world, and retain their divine
natures. The connection does depend
absolutely on the idea that the divine is complete, is total in its nature, is
the ultimate limit of reality, and is the final end. These things have analogues in the world of existence,
and so there is a route of commerce open between the world of the divine and
the world of existence.
Man has connection with the world of the
divine through things and properties which are present in the world of
existence which participate in the nature of the divine. These things include:
completion, totality, the limit, the end, the perfection of a thing, a nature,
a property, or an act, and so on. It also includes infinitive and superlative
action, and also its extreme opposite, inaction. Greatness too, which we found
to be an insufficient concept in the medieval version of an ontological
argument concerning the divine, is also something which may open the way to the
divine. The ancients also included ‘fame’ as one of the properties which connect
man with the divine. We can explore the wide range of concepts and properties
which can connect us with the divine along the way. We shall find that justice, beauty,
magnanimity, ethical and moral perfection, and honour, are also included in
this list.
It is not necessary for us to have a
complete understanding of the divine in order to access aspects of that higher
reality. In fact a focus on particular characteristics, a ‘bracketing’ of the
most relevant aspects of the divine, increases the efficacy of the commerce
with the divine. Thus the intentionality of the supplicant is a factor in the
opening of contact with the divine. There are other ideas associated with the
strengthening of the connection with the divine which we shall explore. These
include reduplication, the striking together of images and concepts, the
collection or heaping up of things, especially where these result in
reduplication of properties; the act of drawing near to the divine, or to the
image of the divine, and so on. The deliberate opposition of ideas and images
is also relevant to the business of establishing a commerce with the divine. For
connection with the divine represents an alteration
of state.
And to reiterate a key point, none of this
proves the reality of God. It merely establishes a range of correspondences
between a concept of God and a hypothetical Being who might or might not have
reality. Instead, the entire intellectual system underpinning polytheism, at
least in its later stages, was rooted in the paradoxical and transcendent
notion of the divine, which necessarily defied human comprehension. So, there
was no proof available, but within this world view, ‘proof’ conclusive to the
human understanding would have demolished the entire edifice.
[1] It is proved by the
fact that it could not ordinarily have happened. This is a tacit admission that
what is real, what is possible, at the level of divine reality, may be entirely
contrary to what we understand as possible in the world of existence.
No comments:
Post a Comment