[This is one of twenty-one essays in the book Man and the Divine, published in August 2018. The book is available in ePub format from leading retailers of eBooks, such as Barnes & Noble, Blio, Kobo, Itunes, Inktera, Smashwords, etc. Information about Man and the Divine can be found here]
The distinction between what is phenomenal, and what is
noumenal, is a major idea in the philosophical outlook of Kant, who pointed out
that what things actually are is not only generally unknown to us, but is in
many cases actually unknowable.
The argument about this can be quite complex, since not only
are there often many simple obstacles to understanding what a thing is, once
the observer starts to think in terms of a contrast between a phenomenal
representation of what that thing is, and the actual nature of the thing in
itself (the noumenon), we become aware of just how little we may know or
understand of the relationship between the two. The world is represented to us
through the senses, and is interpreted in terms of the categories of
understanding which we use to make sense of this information. But how that interpretation relates to what is represented to us in this way is mysterious. Speaking of
representation is a good way of reminding ourselves that how something appears,
and how it is in itself, is a matter of a conflation of the representation of a
thing, and the conventions about what it is, or might be, which exist within
the categories of our understanding.
So when we see a tree, we, as a matter of convention, treat
the tree and its appearance as what the tree is, because in normal
circumstances, there is not likely to be a conflict between our understanding
of what is being represented to us by our understanding of the sense data
available to us. The appearance fits with the categories of knowledge and
understanding which we bring to bear on our experience.
Kant was not the first to observe that there was a
distinction between appearance and reality, and between what is understood of a
phenomenon by convention, and what the real nature of a thing is, This was a
recurring thread in the development of Greek philosophy. Their understanding of
the nature of their world was framed within the context of divine powers and
agencies, so the idea that reality was hidden from the human understanding was
highly developed among the Greeks and other ancient societies.
A question which is sometimes posed to children to
illustrate the idea that the representation of something isn’t the same as what
it is, is: ‘what is the colour of grass?’ The answer will usually be returned quickly, and
be ‘green’. But of course grass isn’t
green. We see grass because the blades reflect particular wavelengths of light
more strongly than others, and absorb some wavelengths. So we don’t see what
colour grass actually is. In fact we are prompted to ask what we mean by an
entity having a property of colour at all. Grass absorbs red transmitted light,
and reflects green light, and those are the properties involved in our
apprehension of the colour of the grass. We don’t know what the colour of grass
in itself is, or even if it is an appropriate question, but we can describe the
processes involved in how we apprehend it.
The categories of our understanding serve us from our
earliest years, but in a simple form. The development of critical intelligence
is the consequence of learning that what is presented to the mind and
understanding is often more complex than it appears to be. What we need from
our understanding at age six is hopelessly inadequate for us at age twenty. We
learn (with the aid of education) to reprogramme the categories of our
understanding so that we can process the information in a more sophisticated
way than we did at six, and are no longer the prisoners of the illusion that
the direct presentation of a thing is the thing itself.
This process of separating ourselves from an interpretation
of the world in terms of simple apprehension is driven initially by the
practical necessities of our existence. But this process does not need to stop
there. Intelligence consists in being able to adjust the categories of our
understanding so that we do not mistake one thing for another. It is a mental
development which might have no end. This is essentially how Kant understood human intellectual development, which he framed (in his Prolegomena) in terms of a
general theory of a priori concepts, not based on empirical sense data, or even a mathematical or geometric understanding of anything in the world. These a
priori concepts can have a relationship with sense data and form in the
phenomenal world, but they are not derived from these objects and constructs,
and can be understood only as concepts entirely stripped of everything which
would give them phenomenal or mathematical reality.
What is proposed in the Prolegomena is that real
intelligence and understanding is what is shown to the mind by the mind alone,
and that these concepts make sense only as purely mental constructs,
manipulated and understood by the mind.
So Kant was talking about understanding what is beyond all
representation, except in terms of mental abstractions, shorn of scalar and
mathematical properties. They are entirely a priori abstractions. The focus of
Kant’s metaphysics therefore is the noumenal reality behind all phenomenal
appearance. This form of metaphysics he regarded as the basis of a scientific
understanding of reality, and that all approaches to understanding the world
through how it presents itself to us are faulty, and will not tell us what we
may wish to know about what lies behind appearance.
No comments:
Post a Comment