I remember analysing the structure of Plato’s The Sophist in 1994, but over time, I
forgot about the argument it contains, or even that I’d made one. I batch-scanned
a lot of paper documents in 2003, and the analysis of The Sophist was one of those. But I didn’t read it again until
recently.
The original document is squibbish, was written quickly, and
was never properly completed or edited. But, knowing what I now know, I’d found
the essential arguments for the ancient priestly understanding of reality, all
collected together in one literary work, without being entirely aware of the
implications of that. It is a little eerie to read this document now, since it
looks far beyond what I was sure of at the time.
What Plato is doing in The
Sophist is what he did in many other dialogues (not all), which was to
include reminders to those who had been trained in theological doctrine what
was important, and to wrap this information up with more or less irrelevant
speculation for the merely curious and uninitiated.
The discussion of the four outlooks on the nature of reality
which feature in The Sophist
represent discussions which took place in the ancient equivalent of the
seminary (it is odd that we don’t have information about the existence of these
institutions in ancient Greece, unless the Academy was exactly that). The
importance of the discussion is that it establishes that the Real is
essentially and necessarily paradoxical. There is the idea of the One, and
there is the experience of the many. If
there is only the One, there is no life, movement or thought. If the many are
real, then it is difficult to understand how there can be something like the
One, which retains its nature, and abides.
Not everyone who participated in these discussions would
have become a priest, because not everyone would have settled for position b),
which, to some casts of mind, would have seemed to be deeply unsatisfactory.
But acceptance of position b) is the one the priestly establishments were
looking for in their candidates.
Why position b)? It is suggested in the course of the dialogue
that it has to be accepted, in order to account for both our intellectual
understanding of the nature of reality, and our experience of the world of
movement and change.
That however is not a philosophical argument. Something is
being glossed over at this point, and we have to look outside The Sophist to understand that. The
answer to this problem is Plato’s concept of The Good, articulated by Socrates in The Timaeus.
Socrates said that:
The ultimate reality, whether it be termed the form of
the Good or given another necessarily inadequate name does not reside in space
- in fact the notion that things have a place is described as "a kind of
bastard reasoning":
we dimly dream and affirm that it is somehow necessary
that all that exists should exist in some spot and occupying some place, and
that which is neither on earth nor anywhere in the Heaven is nothing.
In the Phaedrus Socrates speaks of the
region above heaven,
“never worthily sung by any earthly poet". It is,
however, as I shall tell; for I must dare to speak the truth... the colourless,
formless, and intangible truly existing essence, with which all true knowledge
is concerned, holds this region and is visible only to the mind...
Which means that Socrates is
referring to the concept of the plenum: the reality we experience a partial
representation, a slice, of what is contained in the totality of what is
possible. If the plenum itself is possible, then the experience of change and
motion is also possible. But as a perception.
The point of position b) is
that it recognises the paradoxical nature of reality, and that what is
represented to us is a subjective
representation of Being itself. There is only Being, and the experience of
physical and secular existence is a partial view of what is contained in the
plenum. We see what we see, but it is not reality itself. It is what we can see and understand.
Is this a purely Greek
understanding? I think it isn’t. Pythagoras (according to the Neoplatonists)
spent around twenty years in Egypt imbibing their doctrines, as well as
having discussions with priesthoods in
the Levant and Mesopotamia, while in the service of Cyrus. Some of that went
into Plato’s work, according to the Neoplatonists, though there is also strong
evidence (which I’ve discussed) that ideas familiar to Plato were already
present in archaic Greece.
The blog page which points to
the paper (‘Magic or Magia? Plato’s Sophist’) is at: http://shrineinthesea.blogspot.com/2019/06/magic-or-magia-platos-sophist.html
The link to the file is at the foot of the page. The article has its own DOI.
Thomas Yaeger, June 3, 2019.
No comments:
Post a Comment