[This is an extract from 'Unwritten Doctrine, Ancient Silence', one of twenty-one essays in the book Man and the Divine, published in August 2018. The book is available in ePub format from leading retailers of eBooks, such as Barnes & Noble, Blio, Kobo, Itunes, Inktera, Smashwords, etc. Information about Man and the Divine can be found here]
Plato was quite explicit in the Timaeus that it was not possible to tell all men about ‘the Father of the Gods’. It follows from this that if, as in Plato’s case, doctrine comes from an understanding of the divine, then there must be an unwritten doctrine beneath the written texts which contains at least what makes sense to Plato himself, and perhaps an inner circle of peers or advanced students.*[1]
Plato was quite explicit in the Timaeus that it was not possible to tell all men about ‘the Father of the Gods’. It follows from this that if, as in Plato’s case, doctrine comes from an understanding of the divine, then there must be an unwritten doctrine beneath the written texts which contains at least what makes sense to Plato himself, and perhaps an inner circle of peers or advanced students.*[1]
It is often assumed by students of antiquity
that there is no special importance to be attached to remarks that certain
items of information are to be kept secret and not imparted to the unworthy,
and to the ordinary mortal. This assumption is based on the presumption that there
was, and is not, anything about which it is impossible to speak of, before those
not used to dealing with information about religion and the divine. This is a
curiosity of modern times, in that the ignorance of theology among the moderns
makes it impossible for them to credit the importance of theology in antiquity
- both to those who understood its
subtleties and and those who didn’t.
In other words, it is assumed that what is
proclaimed secret is not something which, within the culture in question, must
necessarily remain secret (otherwise dire consequences might follow), but is
something local to a particular cult or religion, and is an artificially
created object of mystification, created for the benefit of the cult, to
increase the aura of that cult, and to promote its ideology.
There is another possibility which should be considered, if only to clear up the scope of the phenomena we are looking at: if the priests in antiquity proclaimed that the secrets pertaining to the
gods should necessarily remain secret, what might be the nature of such secrets?
Naturally it is not being suggested that all
religious structures and institutions in antiquity would subscribe to what we
might call ‘rational circumspection’ and a necessary element of secrecy. But it
is important to explore the possibility that sometimes, and perhaps for the
most part, as it might turn out if we look closely enough, these structures and
institutions had what they understood as very good reasons for this way of
operating. It is too easy to write off this aspect of ancient life on the
grounds that of course they would say this kind of thing about themselves and
their institution even if there were no rationality at all in the practice.
Certainly ancient religious belief was as subject to political manipulation and
machination as in the modern world, but it does not follow that there was
nothing more substantial to the religions of the ancient world than a purely
ideological tool for a power elite who believed in absolutely nothing (though
it might be perfectly fair to suggest that modern power elites believe in
nothing but power itself).
If we presume the ancients did not believe in the rational sense of their religion and their cultic practices, at least at some level, then a whole raft of other questions would need to be answered, We would have no way, for example, of fathoming why the story of Agamemnon’s sacrifice
of his daughter Iphigenia in order to gain a fair wind for Troy, was credible to an ancient audience, and made some kind of sense.
Clearly the truth is likely to lie somewhere
in between the two extremes of belief and disbelief in the tenets and
imperatives of ancient religion. But if we do not explore belief and its
reasons in antiquity, we can never know detail of the level of rationality in
ancient religion. This is not a problem, if, as is implicit in many modern
studies of ancient religion, we assume that religion is at root an irrational
response to the complexity of both nature and human society. The argument that
there may be a rational component in ancient religions therefore can be
understood as an attempt to elucidate the extent to which this might be true,
and to challenge the conventional view that there is nothing of the sort to be found there.
Plutarch gives some interesting information
about Alexander’s intellectual background in his account of Alexanders career.
He wrote that: ‘It would appear that Alexander received from [Aristotle] not
only his doctrines of Morals, and of Politics, but also something of those more
abstruse and profound theories which these philosophers, by the very names they
gave them, professed to reserve for oral communication to the initiated, and
did not allow many to become acquainted with. For when he was in Asia, and
heard Aristotle had published some treatises of that kind, he wrote to him,
using very plain language to him in behalf of philosophy, the following
letter’:
Alexander to Aristotle greeting. You have not done well to publish your books of oral doctrine; for what is there now that we excel in others in, if those things which we have been particularly instructed in be laid open to all? For my part, I assure you, I had rather excel others in the knowledge of what is excellent, than in the extent of my power and dominion. Farewell.*[2]
This is generally taken to be a reference to
Aristotle’s Metaphysics. However at the time Plutarch was writing,
perhaps the late 1st century C.E., or the early 2nd
century, it is likely that Aristotle’s Metaphysics
had not surfaced as a published work. *[3] It
is unlikely on this account to be a genuine letter. Nevertheless, the passage
reflects the ancient perception of an agrapha, an unwritten and orally
communicated doctrine underlying the public work of both Aristotle’s Lyceum,
and Plato’s Academy.
What could possibly be of such importance to
withhold, and from whom? The story of the prisoners in the Cave in the Republic
of Plato gives the general outline of the problem. The simile involves a group
of men whose only means of apprehending reality in a darkened cave is the
shadows of things cast on the wall by the flames of a fire. For these men,
there is no other reality. Were they to become aware of the fact that they were
not seeing real objects, but only shadowy two-dimensional representations of
real objects, this would cause them to have to restructure their picture of
reality. The problem would be so much worse if they were released from the cave
into the sunlight. Plato invokes the strength of the sun’s light as part of the
simile, and suggests that the prisoners would have to look at the image of the
sun via darkened pools of water, before attempting to gaze on the light of the
sun directly (as if one would ever want to advise this).
In the story of the Cave, the sun is the
image of the Good, the Form of Forms, and the ultimate source of all
representation and experienced reality. Plato, by means of the story of the
Cave and its inhabitants, is illustrating his view that reality is an extremely
complex phenomenon, and that it cannot be understood easily without
preparation. Were the complexity of reality, or rather its understanding, to be
introduced baldly to men unprepared for what they were about to hear and see,
they would be unable to comprehend it for what it was, and might attack those
who were leading them out of the Cave into the sunlight.*[4]
Anyone who has explained technical or
abstract information - which is to some extent counterintuitive in nature - to
someone who has a narrow and concrete understanding of the world and its parts,
will understand something of the problem which Plato is addressing here.
Explaining to an untutored musician that
(for example) the modern piano keyboard has actually been detuned to make the
full range of polyphonic composition possible, is likely to produce an adverse
reaction, despite the fact that it is quite true. The reaction is likely to be complete disbelief, so used have we become
to the tuning of the equal-temperament keyboard.
This of course is a relatively trivial
example. The Good in the writings of Plato is a transcendent concept, beyond
any earthly exemplar, and extremely difficult to communicate even to an
educated and informed audience. Plato is clearly signalling that, beyond the
simple difficultly of explaining the nature of reality to those who, for
whatever reason, have been brought up with a weak and threadbare account of it,
there is a necessary and unavoidable difficulty in understanding the concept of the Good and that the difficulty inheres in the nature of the Good.
The Good, as defined in the work of Plato, is
taken to be Plato’s own conception. Clearly it has something to do with the nature
of the divine, though Plato is often read as if he is speaking purely
philosophically, whatever that might mean in the context of ancient Greece. The
Good is, as Plato discussed the concept, not something which we expect to find
in earlier contexts. The remark of Christ in the Gospels that none should be
called ‘Good,’ but God is of course made several centuries later, and in a
milieu where Greek philosophy was familiar, *[5]
but when, in the book of Genesis, God looked upon his handiwork at the end of
the first week of creation, ‘he saw that it was good.’*[6]
Genesis represents a redaction of earlier texts, probably compiled in the fifth
century B.C.E., in the time of the Persian domination of the near East.
Scholars blink at this reference, and do not see what is there in
the text.*[7] No
rational philosophical concept is involved.
The only public lecture Plato ever gave was
on ‘the Good’. It was not a great popular success, and treated the subject in
such a mathematical way that the audience had great difficulty in understanding
what he was talking about.*[8] We
might be on the right track by suspecting that Plato had no intention of being
understood by the bulk of his audience, and that the matter of his talk was not
intended for the ears of the multitude, in the same way that, contrary to
popular opinion, the public utterances of Christ as reported in the Gospels
were not intended to be understood to those who did not have the ‘ears to
hear’.
As already mentioned, Plato explicitly said
in the Timaeus that it would be impossible to explain the ‘Father of the Gods’
to men. This was partly for the reason that the transcendent nature of the
divine is beyond our capacity to put adequately into words, but also because,
as illustrated in the story of the Cave in the Republic, the uninitiated
individuals who cannot apprehend the nature of the Good directly live in a
world of phantoms and illusions. Their reason is necessarily clouded because of
that fact, since it must be impossible to come to sound judgements on the basis
of a procession of phantoms bearing no constructive and causal relationships
with one another.
So Plato’s attitude to the ordinary citizens of Attica, of
Greece, and of the wider world, was dismissive: they had no constructive
contribution to make to the elucidation of the nature of reality, and it would
be hazardous to give them details of the nature of the Good, since there could
be no way of predicting what they would do with that information. They might
even wish to imprison or kill those who might be foolish enough to wish to
release them from their prison world of dreams and false opinion.
We know that secrecy was an important part of
Greek cult, though much of religious life in Greece seems very open in comparison
with other parts of the ancient world. Exclusion was an important aspect of
religious practice in Greece as it was anywhere else – certain groups would not
be allowed to attend religious worship, or at certain times, just as in Attica
certain groups were excluded from participation in the political life of the
polis. Yet the rites of the Olympian Gods have not come down to us, which makes
discussion of Greek religious life very difficult for scholars, who are reduced
to talking in the most general terms about the meaning of the Olympians to the
Greeks. We do know about civic responsibilities in connection with the cults of
the Gods, often from later periods than the classical, and from Greek cities in
Anatolia during Hellenistic times, in the form of liturgies which had to be
paid for by prominent individuals within the community, in order to cement
their participation in both the cult and the life of the city.
From the point
of view of a purely sociological analysis of ancient Greek culture, this information
is perhaps more valuable that the detail of the liturgies themselves – however
here we are looking at the ideas which form the basis of religious
life. We do have hymns to the gods which were an important part of ritual in
the mystery cults. These mostly come from Roman Egypt, and have late features,
as might be expected. But otherwise they tell us something of the likely
importance of a wide range of Gods in cults which were well established in the
early history of Greece, say from the time of Pythagoras to Herodotus.
Pythagoras’ own doctrines were taught as part of the life of an exclusive cult,
and Herodotus mentions various cults in the course of his history. However,
each time he makes reference to an important piece of cultic practice of some
significance for his narrative, he makes it clear that he is not divulging that
practice in the text, but is relying on the reader (or listener, if the text
was being read in public, as it seems to have been at the time of its
composition). He says something like: ‘those who are familiar with the
mysteries of the Kaberoi at Samothrace will know what I mean’. This is of
course extremely annoying for modern scholars, who at one and the same time
know that there is some interesting reference being made, and that they have no
idea what it is. So there is (or rather was), an esoteric reading of the text
possible, as opposed to the surface reading which we now have to make, except
in the rare cases where we can supply the deficiency.
Clearly the esoteric reading of the Histories
of Herodotus made sense to his readers, and made the work richer in antiquity
than it is now.
If we move forward in time to the
neo-Platonist Porphyry, who was a pupil of Plotinus, and look at his work on
the images of the Gods, we can see that the same imperative of secrecy
operates. Porphyry uses the conceit of a discourse within the precincts of a
temple, in order to explain something of the import of images within a sacred
context. Those who have only profane knowledge are asked to leave, which says
loud and clear that there is another level of understanding, a sacred understanding of religious imagery beyond that available in the world of common
opinion.*[9] Of
course Porphyry is delivering this imaginary discourse in the form of a written
text, which is not subject to the kind of restrictions possible in the context
of a guarded temple. So Porphyry’s text has to do two things at once: it has
to reveal and not reveal at the same time. Going back briefly to the
supposed letter from Alexander to Aristotle, found in Plutarch’s Life of
Alexander, it is interesting to read Aristotle’s supposed answer to
Alexander, in which he defended his action in publishing the esoteric doctrines
of the Lyceum in the full light of day by saying precisely that they were
‘published, but not published.’ In other words, Aristotle was claiming (in
Plutarch’s text) that though the text of the Metaphysics or whichever work it was) contained
information relating to the esoteric doctrines of the Lyceum, communicated
formerly in person to Aristotle’s pupils, it did not publish the doctrines in
a form in which they were to be properly understood.
The question might be asked in that case (if this exchange of letters was real,
rather than being a way in which Plutarch could make clear his attitude to the
nature of Aristotle’s Lyceum, and a supposed esoteric level of Alexander’s
imperial mission), why were the doctrines published at all? The same question
might be asked of Plato’s writings, since he makes it very clear within the
corpus that the invention of writing as a means of communicating important
information was a great disaster, since formerly memory had been cultivated,
and memory was of great importance to the understanding of the world.
Our natural response to esoteric levels of
meaning is, in the absence of clear and overt information about these levels of
meaning, to pass over these levels as absent, and of no consequence to us and
our understanding. Both Plato and Aristotle published their texts as an aide-memoires
of sorts,*[10]
principally for those who already had an understanding of the doctrines being
alluded to in the course of Aristotle’s text.
We do not have this kind of intimate association with the doctrines at
the heart of these texts, and so it would seem to be utterly impossible to
penetrate whatever these doctrines might be. *[11]
....
....
[End of extract]
[1]
That Plato had an unwritten doctrine is not itself an unusual view among Plato
scholars – over the past hundred years a large proportion have taken this view
– Paul Shorey being an example. However reasons for holding that Plato had an
unwritten doctrine vary. Mostly the view arises because otherwise it is
difficult to find coherence in the Platonic corpus. So the idea of an agrapha
arises as something which contains the missing pieces in the structure.
[2] Plutarch Lives: Alexander.
[3] There is an excellent account of the progress toward publication of Aristotle’s manuscripts in the Penguin edition of his Nicomachean Ethics. Like almost all of Aristotle’s works which we possess, this work appears to be constructed out of notes made by Aristotle himself, or by his students. At least one passage in the Nicomachean Ethics clearly duplicates the content of another, if not in the same words, which suggests strongly an imperfect collation of notes by several hands by a student editor.
[4]
This is a clear allusion to the fate of Plato’s teacher Socrates, who was
accused of corrupting the youth of Athens.
[5]
Christ may allude to the story of Socrates and the cup of Hemlock in the Gospel
of John.
[6]
Book of Genesis.
[7]
Of course the determinant of what meaning is intended by the reference to what
is Good is the context. And the context of a creation by the separation of
waters and the creation of a vault of heaven does not immediately suggest the
presence of a philosophical level. Near eastern kingship employed both the concept
of the Good in terms of a final cause with which the King sought to be
identified, and the mastery of the forces of chaos and order, symbolised by the
disposition of the waters of the Apsu.
[8]
Cherniss, Harold.
[9]
Though there are important differences in the doctrines of Plato and the
neo-Platonists which it is important to observe in discussion, both Plato and
the neo-Platonists were at one with respect to the idea that understanding was
a property of the divine, and that lesser mortals, the uninitiated and merely
common, were lesser beings precisely because of their greater distance from
understanding.
[10]
Plato’s account of the importance of memory makes it clear that any unwritten
doctrine would be unlikely to be committed to writing, and therefore written
documents must make sense as allusive texts.
[11]
The Cambridge History of Early Medieval Philosophy mentions this
difficulty, referring particularly to the works of the Neoplatonists. The
presence of an esoteric background is acknowledged, but since there seems to be
no way in to this background in the absence of a key, the only course of action
is to evaluate the material in terms of the surface text. A.C. Lloyd, The
Cambridge History of Early Medieval Philosophy.
........