The following text concerns the question of whether or not there was a philosophical basis for the development of religious concepts in antiquity, informing ritual, liturgy, divination, sacrifice, and the worship of images; and therefore, as a consequence, philosophy was not the exclusive possession of the Greeks in the 1st millennium B.C.E.
This argument of course turns the received view of the historical relationship between religion and philosophy upside down: we like to think that the development of philosophy was a practical response to religion as it became an outworn and irrational phenomenon, which preceded a more scientific approach to phenomena and nature. If such a sequence is in fact falsely inferred, and undermined by the evidence, then we have some rethinking to do.
The text references both my book The Sacred History of Being (2015), and the contents of Understanding Ancient Thought (2017). It is one of twenty-one essays in the book Man and the Divine, published in August 2018. The book is available in ePub format from leading retailers of eBooks, such as Barnes & Noble, Blio, Kobo, Itunes, Inktera, Smashwords, etc. Information about Man and the Divine can be found here]
Thomas Yaeger, April 28, 2017
What
has been argued in part one of the book (The Sacred History of Being) is that ideas of Being, of the nature
of reality, and the divine, were once understood in terms of conjecture about
the reality (or otherwise) of the one and the many. These follow on from the
initial question, which is: why is there something rather than nothing? Plato’s
argument, following on from propositions made by Parmenides, who declared that
we should look only to the one, and that only the one truly exists, is the most
sophisticated of all discussions in antiquity concerning why there should be
something rather than nothing.
Plato
argues that we should always look to the ‘one true thing’. This is different
from saying only the one exists, or only the one is truly real.
J.G.
Frazer was very dismissive of Greek questions concerning the one and the many,
saying that they constituted ‘popular questions of the day’. The argument of
Parmenides remained entirely undiscussed.
But then he argued that questions concerning Being were entirely barren,
since nothing could be predicated of Being.
This
of course is a spectacular instance of intellectual blindness, by which the
richness of the intellectual matrix of ancient Greek thought was spirited into
nothingness. We like to see Plato’s discussion of Being as the surfacing of a
human capacity to grapple with abstract ideas, and the marker of our
emancipation from irrational ideas about the world and the gods. For Frazer,
Plato was as guilty of intellectual error as any of his contemporaries, as well
as his predecessors.
In
late Hellenistic times, there seems to have been a very poor grasp of the
context of the development of philosophy around the Mediterranean. Nods were
made toward the notion that the discipline of philosophy might not have been
first developed in Greece, including (tellingly) at the beginning of Diogenes
Laertius' Lives of the Philosophers.
Plato after all argued against the idea that this was so in the
Protagoras, saying that it was of a great age – perhaps contemporary with the
arrival of peoples from Egypt, who settled in the Peloponnese, and in also
Crete.
He also presented Solon in discussion with Egyptian priests in the pages
of the Timaeus, who found the Greeks very young, and not conversant with
knowledge ‘hoary with age’. Aristotle (in
his Metaphysics) presented the common sense view that philosophy was first
developed in a place where there was a leisured class, with the time and
resources to think about philosophical questions. He may have had Egypt in
mind, since Egypt had professionalised priesthoods.
Later philosophers such as
Porphyry suggested that key parts of Pythagorean doctrine came west to Greece
from Babylon, in the late sixth century (Plato references details of this
doctrine, without connecting it explicitly to Pythagoras). We have also seen
that aspects of that doctrine can be found elsewhere in Herodotus (concerning
Solon), and also in Homer’s Iliad (Book 18), where a number of key details
associated with the doctrine are run together in close order, without being explained.
The former Priest of Bel at Babylon, Berossus, moved to Athens, probably during
the reign of Ptolemy Philadelphus in Egypt, and wrote about Babylonian history
and philosophy, describing their system of knowledge as based on an initial
plenum, using the image of a sage emerging daily from the sea, granting
knowledge to man about the sciences, agriculture, and the practical arts.
Not
much of this was of use to the Enlightenment agenda, which preferred to look at
the development of philosophy in Greece as the first beginnings of a rational
understanding of the world. And so the information was deprecated and ignored.
The phrase ‘I doubt that’ is a dangerous one in the classics community. It is a
way of saying ‘this is not the consensus view of scholars and the profession’.
Usually no discussion follows, since the opinion is usually an opinion of the
worth (or otherwise) of evidence. Scholars weigh evidence, and they do so (they
are convinced) with better tools than were available to ancient scholars. The judgement
is fitted to modern requirements. So, as a result, it is clear that it is
unlikely that Solon visited Egypt, and that Pythagoras visited Babylon. Tread
carefully, or your credibility as a scholar may be in doubt.
Thus,
the scholarly consensus is that philosophy is an autochthonous development. Why
in Greece? The ‘Greek Genius’ won’t cut the mustard any more, at least by
itself, but I have heard it said by people who should know better. But during
the high days of the Enlightenment, and the beginnings of what became the
fully-fledged discipline of Classics, that is what the scholars wanted.
Something pure and out of the orbit of other cultures, which, by definition,
had no philosophy or anything which would measure up to something like rational
thought.
Sometimes
history is built backwards. It isn’t just a matter of looking to the historical
record and starting from that. History always has been in part about critical
scrutiny of sources and judgements, even among the Greeks. But as Bernal
pointed out in the first volume of his Black Athena, the critical revision was
wholesale, with the purpose of creating a representation of the true origins of
European civilisation as it entered the period of the Enlightenment.
That
was the agenda. To reinterpret the past, and in terms of a rational and
enlightened understanding of the world. Hence, Diderot wrote not just about
ideas and philosophy in his Encyclopedia, but also about the arts and crafts.
The latter may have been wrapped up with myth, folklore, and superstition, but
they were still essential to the rational life of man, so these were also added
to the Encyclopedia. Everything from the past which served some purpose, or
which could be made to serve some purpose within the rational enlightenment
model of reality, was critically examined, and reworked to fit what was
intended to become a new understanding of man and his place in a new world of
reason. A new understanding of how man might live.
As
I point out in the chapter ‘Logical Modality in Classical Athens’ there are in
fact two logical modalities present in the writings of Plato and Aristotle.
Aristotle is mostly (though not always) concerned with the modality which has
come down to us as the basis of formal logic. Plato is clearly aware of this
modality, but, though no scholar has dared to identify the other modality as
logical, it is. It is simply that to us, it does not describe relationships
which should be described as logical. Plato thought otherwise, and talks about
this logical modality often, in the Republic and in the Timaeus. It is
connected with the doctrine of wholes and totalities, and is the basis of
explaining how things may participate in other things, which is not a pattern
of ideas which fits with Aristotle’s general understanding of logic.
Why
is this important? Simply put, it matters because it is the basis of the Greek
understanding of how transcendent reality relates to secular and physical
existence, which was a matter of great significance in the middle of the first
millennium B.C.E. The doctrine also
underpins the understanding of both transcendent reality, and the idea of the
immanence of the divine. It also points to a rather strange conclusion about
the nature of the reality in which we live and think.
It
might be imagined therefore that this would be the subject of a great deal of
scholarship. In fact there is very little on the subject. The dialogues in
question have been written about endlessly over the last two centuries, but,
though Plato’s discussion is noted, the fact that it is a form of logical
modality is not acknowledged, and the conclusions which might follow from
treating it as such, do not follow, and are therefore not discussed. It is
treated as it is presented – as mathematical and geometrical metaphors for how
things might possess some form of congruence with each other.
As
I wrote in the chapter ‘Sweet Song of Swans’, there is very little appetite for
attempting to understand Plato in his own terms. When he talks about
transcendent reality, this is treated as some sort of literary fiction, which
has no necessary properties of its own. When Plato talks about the Forms, this
also is treated as a species of literary fiction, which Plato himself
demolished in his Parmenides and in the Sophist. Wnen Plato discusses the soul,
it turns out that it is something which has the property of being connected
with the Form of the Good, and so knowledge is acquired by the activation of
that connection. We have forgotten what we knew (apparently) through the shock
of physical birth, but it is possible for us to reacquire this knowledge. Deriving all knowledge from the Form of the
Good is also seen as a bafflingly impenetrable notion, since he talks about
ascending purely in the mind from Form to Form, and then descending back to the
world of physical reality, Form by Form, and says this is the only way to
acquire genuine knowledge.
How
can real knowledge be acquired in this way? Why should Plato argue like
this? How can any of this make sense to
us?
It
makes very little sense to us, because we have lost the original doctrinal
context of his discussions, and we are not that interested in attempting to
recover what we can of that context, even for the purposes of a better
scholarly understanding of what he is talking about. So the study of Plato
languishes in the seminar room, taught and discussed from generation to
generation by people who have no clear idea of what Plato meant. Books and
papers are published, which clear up a minor detail here, discuss another one
there, but do not leave us much the wiser.
We can understand the range of existing
discussion about Plato in terms of what scholars do not or cannot
understand about Plato, and their attempts to fit what they think they
understand about his work into some kind of modern intellectual and critical frame.
It is their minds, and the categories of their own understanding which are
problematic, not the obscurity of Plato’s ideas.
Other
than that, reading Plato at least serves to teach us something about how we
used to think, and how we may think, even if we understand very little of what
he is saying.
One
of the principal reasons we cannot easily understand Plato is down to the loss
of an understanding of that alternative logical modality. So a major concern of
this book is to restore knowledge of it, and a basic comprehension of why it is
important. Not just for our understanding of Plato himself, but also for our
understanding of his cultural context; the context in which philosophy was
understood to be of inestimable value; and also for an understanding of some
very strange things about the ancient world, which are all the stranger because
(it seems) they made sense in antiquity (sacrifice, divination, idolatry,
prophecy, omens, oracles, etc.).
One of
the most valued books in my library is Religion & Magic: Approaches and
Theories. The author is Graham Cunningham, who is a specialist in the ancient
Near East. Anthropology is a relatively young discipline, though crowded with
many points of view. Cunningham’s book covers the whole range of these, at
least in terms of summarising the views of those who first suggested those
theoretical approaches. He divides the approaches into several sections, which
are 1. German pioneers, 2 Early Intellectualist approaches, 3 Emotionalist
approaches, 4 Phenomenological Approaches, 5 Structural Functional Approaches,
6 Symbolic Approaches, 7 Recent Intellectualist Approaches, 8 Structural
approaches, 9, Cognitive Approaches, 10, and finally Feminist Approaches.
All of
these approaches were developed and used without any meaningful distinction
being made between ancient cultural phenomena and cultural phenomena of modern
times. I write carefully here, since there are unpleasant assumptions in the
discipline of anthropology, which have not yet been rooted out entirely.
Anthropology was founded in the early nineteenth century, and the presumptions
of the time are necessarily locked into the work of the pioneers. Many of these
presumptions are still implicit, and can be called into the light of day if you
scratch the modern anthropologist in the course of discussion. The fact is that
an unfounded equation was early made between the cultures of antiquity and the
world of the primitive and the savage in the modern world (which the Classicist
D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson referred to as ‘running folklore to the death’).
So
Cunningham’s book covers two centuries of thought about culture, civilization,
religion, magic and ritual. All premised on the assumptions, understanding and
categories of knowledge of those living and working in those two centuries.
Nothing about those matters is covered from earlier centuries. It is as if the
study of human culture, human thought, and the nature of man himself, began
only in Hegel’s study, and nothing of worth came before Hegel.
I could
digress here, and lay out what came before in detail, but that is for another
time. I will allow myself to say that Plato had something else to add to the
pot, which is not covered in Cunningham’s survey; the Neoplatonists (who
thought of themselves as Platonists, but we will not let them be what they are)
would have had added the same thing to the pot, as would some of the early
Gnostic writers.
The Platonists of the Italian and English Renaissances
understood what Plato was writing about, at least for the most part, and would
be shocked that, not only do we not understand Plato, but that we have chosen
to explain human culture in terms of a fundamental stupidity about the way
reality works, and with a complete disregard for the way the human mind was
once understood to engage with that reality.
In
short, religion is seen by all anthropologists and sociologists in negative terms (at least professionally –
what they choose to believe in private is a separate matter), as something
baleful and poisonous to human culture and human thought, except to the extent
that religious belief provides social cohesion, ideology, and rules of social
behaviour.....