In my middle twenties, after exposure to Taoist philosophical ideas and
other philosophical systems of the east, I was struck by the way in which
western ideas and modes of thought often seem to have been shaped in oppostion
to the kinds of thought found in the east – almost as if western thought was a
construct based on the avoidance of certain forms of thinking, and of certain
areas of interest. [1] Western
philosophical thought is (for example) not interested in questions of creation,
having ceded all interest in these areas to physics and its related field of
study, cosmology, as if this is an appropriate arena in which the physicists
and cosmologists might usefully operate. Western philosophy is also not much
interested in areas of reality which pass beyond an understanding based on
truth tables.
The contemporary disparity and even antipathy between eastern and western
philosophical approaches was obvious: what I did not then understand, at least
with any clarity, was that a sustained campaign had been under way in the west
to purge the western philosophical tradition of its connection with the east,
and to remove, through source criticism and other means, as many instances as
possible of eastern modes of thought. Thus accounts of connections between east
and west, and the supposed journeys of Pythagoras, and Solon to Egypt and the
Near East became ‘unlikely’, and it became possible to dismiss (for example) an
eastern origin of the cult of the Kabiroi in Thrace, and also to remove
semitic etymologies wholesale from the principal linguistic reference work of
the classicists.[2] Examples of western
thinking within categories of understanding and experience familiar to eastern
civilisations are now conventionally termed ‘mystical’ rather than
philosophical, and the writers of such texts were eventually abandoned to the
theologians, who have – also as a result of the western enlightenment -
suffered marginalisation in the west. This modern purification of the cultural
development of Greece during the sixth to the fourth centuries B.C.E took place
despite the fact that it was impossible to deny heavy cultural borrowing from
Egypt and the Near East in the eighth and seventh centuries B.C.E., because of
the sheer quantity of archaeological evidence. [3]
The narrative history of western philosophy created since
the enlightenment has a marked aversion to an acknowledgement of eastern modes
of thought within the western philosophical tradition during a period of two
and a half millennia, so that the contemporary philosopher George Melhuish was
able to write that in the whole tradition, including the Greeks, only six
philosophers had explored the paradoxical aspects of reality. What has actually
happened in the west is that the idea of philosophy has been redefined. What is
eastern in the western tradition is not regarded as philosophy. And the eastern
philosophical tradition, like the ancient intellectual tradition before the
rise of classical Athens, is however generally regarded in the west as ‘not
really philosophy’. No problem is encountered as long as the eastern tradition
is not taught in western universities on the same footing as the western
tradition, and it is in fact uncommon for the two to be taught together.
There have of course been more than six ‘western’
thinkers in two and a half millennia who have dealt with the notion of the
universe as a paradoxical matrix, but most are nowadays not regarded as
philosophical thinkers and writers. [4] It occurred to me
that, if this process of marginalisation was the product of an antipathy to the
eastern intellectual tradition, in that it was an antipathy to views of the
universe in which the Aristotelian laws of thought were understood to be
inadequate to articulate the nature of reality, then a similar process might be
in play regarding the intellectual tradition among the presocratics in Greece.
This was the motive for looking again rather closely at the whole tradition
of philosophy in Greece from its earliest manifestations up until the death of
Aristotle. And rather than reviewing the material with the view of creating a
coherent narrative enshrining a received view of the significance and place of
the Greek intellectual tradition in relation to modern western conceptions of
the role of philosophy, it was important to look for oriental modes of thought
in the history of Greek thought.
Naturally since I was looking for a process in the marginalisation of
aspects of the Greek intellectual tradition running parallel to the
marginalisation of all things eastern, it was also important to look at the
same time at the intellectual tradition in the ancient east. This study
focusses on ancient Assyria, and its cultural parallels with ancient Greece.
There are other parallels, of which I am well aware – the Greeks made great
play of their interest in ancient Egypt, and their indebtedness to that culture
in many significant respects. Though Egypt is mentioned from time to time, the
main focus here is usually elsewhere. [5]
We have arrived at our current impasse in our understanding of the ancient
world to some significant extent because of an enlightenment inspired
redefinition of the meaning of philosophy. One of the functions of this study
is to reorient the term ‘philosophy’ so that we may understand once again the
nature of our intellectual history. The enlightenment, despite its name, sought
to expel many things into shadowlands, rather than bring them into the light:
part of its purpose was to close off aspects of our collective intellectual
history which, in the eighteenth century, were seen as irrational and foolish.
The confident and forward-looking minds of the enlightenment wished to
transform these undesirable aspects of our intellectual legacy into the misshapen
and disordered products of primitive minds, making them into pathologies. It
did not occur to the savants of eighteenth century Europe that, if aspects of
the Greek tradition seemed incomprehensible and barbaric, characteristics
shared with most of the intellectual tradition of the near east, this might be
because something very complex and very subtle was going on. Instead, they
assumed that the incomprehensibility of the ancient world, the baffling nature
of much of its literature, iconography and cults, was the result of an
incipient and endemic incoherence, the absence of rational modes of thought,
and even the downright stupidity of ancient peoples.
After some two hundred years of critical
scholarship, some of which has pushed whole rafts of material into an outer
darkness in which such materials cannot be readily used as comparative evidence
for the study of other stages of the same civilisation, the available evidence
for recasting our model of antiquity and its intellectual life is in disarray.
The Neoplatonists have nothing to tell us about Greek philosophy or religion in
the classical period, the texts of Plato can tell us nothing about the nature
and detail of Greek religion (and nothing about theology – as we now understand
it, since it remains to be invented); Homer and Hesiod remain principal sources
for an understanding of the Greek view of the Gods. [6] The evidence for the existence of a philosophical outlook in other cultures
around the Mediterranean, both textual and archaeological, which has surfaced
since the early nineteenth century, remains unsubject to any significant degree
of comparison. Greece is the great source of intellectual influence, but (it
seems) did not itself participate in the intellectual life of the world during
its high period. [7]
Contrary to prevailing understanding, the practice of philosophy can be
detected in art, literature and cult, and a philosophically grounded theology
of the world predates the application and adaptation of Greek philosophical
concepts to the creation of Christian theology in the first centuries of the
modern era; and these more ancient theologies are rooted in what is in fact a
philosophical analysis of, and discourse concerning, the nature of reality.
[1] In the west it seems absurd to describe Taoism as a
philosophical system. We think of systematic thought as necessarily having
Newtonian mathematical rigour based on unambiguous axioms. Thus Taoist thought
is, for the western mind, to be bracketed with mystical thought – a mode of
speculation shorn of precision and clarity. In fact however, Taoist thought
proceeds on the assumption that there is an important difference between the
way in which reality presents itself to us and the nature of reality itself.
Taoism simply assumes that reality
cannot be reduced to unambiguous
description. It is systematic in that every aspect of Taoist thought derives
from the understanding that the nature of reality in itself necessarily
transcends its presentation.
[2] The etymologies disappeared from the ninth edition of
Liddell and Scott’s dictionary, during a much overdue cull of linguistic
speculation which had accumulated in the work.
[3] This period is known as the Orientalising period, and
is explained in terms of the Greeks looking outward before the Greek genius
refashioned what it had acquired into something properly Greek. Whatever that
might mean.
[4] They needn’t be listed here, but many within the
western mystical tradition fall into this category. Nicholas of Cusa is one of
the most interesting and intelligent of writers during the past two millennia,
but it is possible to study philosophy in a western university without even a
cursory examination of one of his texts. Bertrand Russell’s History of
Western Philosophy omits any mention of him. Because of his high position
in the Catholic Church he is regarded as a theological writer.
[5] In fact the initial exploration of the possibility of
a detectable presence of the theory of Being in cultures antecedent to Greece
focussed heavily on Egypt, which is the culture most often explicitly referred
to by the Greeks as the source of philosophy as well as religion among the
Greeks.
[6] There is an interesting divergence between historians
and anthropologists in terms of the way evidence is used. Historians of the
ancient world are the inheritors of the division between the classical world
and the later Hellenistic and Roman periods, erected by the classicists. The
anthropologists by contrast bring a different set of preconceptions and
scholarly tradition to the same material, and cheerfully make comparisons
between classical, Hellenistic, and neo-platonic ideas. As long as they don’t
infer anything about the textual and cultural dependencies of one to the other,
they don’t get into trouble.
[7] That is, Greece within the classical period tends to
be treated as if it is a purely autochthonous ferment of ideas, entirely
uninfluenced by the world of the ancient Near East, Europe, and North Africa.
This was once a more serious isolation than is now the case, since it is now
recognised that the evidence will not in fact support it, but an underlying
anxiety about the purity of the Greek achievement still remains.
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDelete