On a rainy day in spring 1993 I attended a talk by the sociologist Harry
Collins at the Edinburgh Science Festival. The subject of the talk was the
sociological aspects of scientific investigation. One of his subjects was the
observational confirmation of Einstein’s theory of relativity through the
displacement of star positions by the gravitational field of the Sun. This was
observed first during an eclipse in 1919. Photographs taken during that eclipse
under the supervision of the astronomer Arthur Eddington indeed showed stellar
displacement, but not all of the plates taken showed displacements in accord
with the prediction of the theory. Some showed stellar displacements up to two
times what was required by the theory.
The point of discussing these photographs was to
illustrate the heavy subjective component involved in the identification of
reliable evidence. The plates represented a range of displacements, and from
these the plates used to supply the data to verify the theory were chosen. The
plates which were rejected were not rejected because they contained false data,
but because they contained data outside the range in which the data which will
support the theory ought to be found. This is simply a feature of experimental
and observational data – not all data which is collected, for a variety of
reasons, points the researcher in the right direction. The researcher has to
have a nose for the right data. [1] It is this
subjective element in the identification of quality evidence which makes good
science so hard to do. If the researcher does not have a nose for selecting his
data, other researchers will soon tear his work apart.
Harry Collins is of course famous for his subversive view of science as a
social construct. In other words, the rules of science are set by the
practitioners and those living and working within the paradigm in which science
and scientific activity have meaning. In a sense this is a reapplication of the
Greek notion of the importance of convention in determining how things are, and
how they are understood. I do not share the extreme view of some sociologists
that all of science is a social construct without any essential root in an
apparently objective and public reality – the inverse square law for example,
was not conjured into existence as something required for our model of reality.
Though it is perfectly true to say that the idea of the laws of physics which
describes the inverse square law is a social construct.
In any case, it seemed that Harry Collins was not attacking the essentially
rational character of the practice of science. Rather he was illustrating the
complexity of the activity.
Which made the closing part of his talk deeply shocking. What happened was that he put a high contrast
image on an easel – of the type where a spotted dalmation is photographed
against rough ground, so that the outline of the dog disappears, and the eye
has to determine the nature of the image from other than the obvious
clues. What the image seemed to show (to
me) all too obviously was a very conventional representation of Christ with
detail represented in fairly low resolution chunks, against a similarly
textured background. He asked for a show of hands from those who thought they
could recognise the image, and almost exactly half of the audience responded.
Apparently all of those who responded recognised the nature of the image. After
telling the audience about what the representation was supposed to indicate, he
pointed out various features of the image for those who were unable to pick out
the embedded image of Christ. He then asked those who had been unable to see
the image before it was described, if they could now see it. Not one said
that they could.
The impact of this response does not entirely depend on whether or not it
was an honest one. It might simply be that the second group were still unable
to see the image presented to them, or they might have chosen to remain
unseeing after the details of the image were described. The surprise for me
came because the representation was not publicly recognised and acknowledged
through its description. What is most shocking about this is that what was
seen by some was apparently impossible to bring to the notice of the other half
of the audience, for whatever reason, and therefore it could not be brought
into a discussion bridging the whole group. It was possible for some to
apprehend it directly, but for others, not to have any perception of it they
were willing to acknowledge, even by description.
An explanation for the invisibility of the image to half of the audience
can be attempted. The image was highly abstract, and required the viewer to
have an easy facility with abstraction, and to infer details which ought to be
present, but, owing to the low resolution of the image, were not in fact
present. Some people are constituted in this way; they can grasp the whole of
something without having all of the details. This is the essence of the
facility required when decisions have to be made where not all of the relevant
facts are available: it is the capacity to make synthetic judgements. Those who
could not see the image, even after it was described and its details pointed
out, may not have the synthetic facility, at least not in the same way and to the
same degree. They do not make the inferential jump from what can be seen to
what might be there, even as an experimental or playful process, after which
they might return to more certain inferences. The information for them simply
is not present, and so they do not see the image.
This is not a matter of intelligence and unintelligence, but of different
kinds of reasoning. One is synthetic in nature, the second is analytic.
Analytic is painstaking, precise, missing the minimum number of steps. The
former is intuitive, generalising, and skipping as many steps (in the first
instance) as is practical. Neither by itself allows sound judgement about
whatever reality is in the frame, but though analytic thought cannot put
together the grand picture, the faculty is essential in supplying the
evidential infrastructure to a hypothesis. Likewise, without the synthetic
faculty, there will be no grand picture to motivate the pursuit of the right
kind of evidence.
To this extent at least our intellectual
apprehension of reality is subjective, and subject to the collective will of
the society in which evidence is collected, examined, and arranged in its
support. The right evidence now is not necessarily the same as the right
evidence yesterday, or tomorrow.
As things stand, the argument of this book is on the edge of what it is
possible to discuss in the modern west. It addresses the nature and properties
of Being - an issue which has long been abandoned except as the subject of dry academic
exercise. Being is as far from the centre of our social and ideological engines
as it is possible to be, except where the question is abandoned to those for
whom rationality is of less importance than faith. [2]
It is nevertheless a legitimate subject for rational discussion, even if we are
unaccustomed to the effort involved, and currently disinclined to rate
questions of Being as of any worth.
It is now a commonplace of scholarly understanding that the development of
modern science from the renaissance onward has to be understood against the
background of late medieval and renaissance magic: here I argue that, in a
similar way, the roots and early development of philosophy lie in the religious
cults of both Greece and the ancient Near East. We cannot develop our
understanding of the early development of philosophy unless we recognise its
origins in the environment of religious cult, and that it has its origins in
cultic practice and thought, both in Greece and further afield.
Not everyone will accept the argument which follows in the chapters of this
book, irrespective of whatever coherence and competitive plausibility it may
have. Some of those who will reject it will do so, not because they cannot
understand the argument as presented, but because they do not see the need for
the case at all. For them, the readjustment of our perspective on our
past will seem like a completely unnecessary and even undesirable complication
of an already coherent picture of the world. There is little I can do about this,
except to outline the case as clearly as possible, in the hope that some
aspects of the importance of this subject, and its tortured history over
at least four millennia, will become visible once more.
The Context of Being
‘…we are estranged from
ancient Near Eastern thought by the sway which Greek philosophy and biblical
ethics hold over our own…’[3] - Henri Frankfort
‘Being’ is a concept which, over time, and to different groups, has meant
different things. It can be applied to things which exist, such as human beings
and inanimate objects, which exist physically in space and time, at least for a
while, or it can refer to that state which some presume to have its reality
beyond the world of existence. Clearly, if Being can be defined both as
something which has come-to-be, as well as something which perpetually ‘is’ and
does not come-to-be, it is clear that it is a concept which depends for its
meaning very much what the context dictates it is.
Sometimes the property ‘existence’ is attributed to a thing to indicate
that ‘it is’, or that it has Being. In which case the meaning of the object’s
Being is that it has the property of existence. The phrase ‘things which exist’
might be used to refer to a vast range of objects and living beings, from the
atom, through bacteria, through man, all the way to the idea of God. Just to
say that something is ‘a thing which exists’ does not at all indicate whether
this thing which exists has the properties of things which come-into-being in
the physical world, or whether the thing which exists has its existence without
the properties of things which come-to-be in the physical world. If we speak of
God in a way which implies a physical existence, by describing God as an
existent Being, will other people understand what we mean and agree?
Other ideas are associated with the notion of Being. It is possible to
speak of an existence which is transcendent, meaning that it is of a nature
which is beyond the nature of a physical existence, if we choose to use the
idea of transcendence in this way. The
nature of the existence of a transcendent God, for example, is of a different
nature from a God who is not transcendent of the nature of the physical world.
We could however use the term ‘transcendent’ in such a way as to indicate
that the concept of God merely referred to a relative status within the same
physical world as beings and objects in the world which do not have a divine
nature. When Hollywood gossip columnists referred to Marilyn Monroe as a
‘goddess’, they were using the term to indicate a relative status of the
actress, rather than attributing to her a genuine divinity (whatever they would
have understood by that). However they might also have been indicating by the
use of the term a certain physical perfection, and perfection is another
quality which is sometimes regarded as a property of God.
If we regard God as a concept which has its transcendent reality beyond the
world of physical existence, does that mean we would be correct to suggest that
God has no existence, since God is not present in the physical world?
What we find discussed in the writings of the Greeks is an idea of Being
which is regarded as transcending the secular world, in that it is apart from
the world of time and space, and has different characteristics and qualities.
Since it does not participate in time, at least as far as we understand it, it
is eternal, and ultimately beyond time. It is however the ultimate, unmoving,
unchanging, indivisible reality which stands behind the moving world of change and
multiplicity. This reality gives rise, in some mysterious way, to the world of
appearance in which we all live. [4]
Why do people think like this? Not everyone one does. Some people pursue an
explanation of reality which is structured on a framework of the known, such as
empirically observed and verified laws, and precedent. This is an essentially
analytical approach to reality, which does not strive to understand why the
world of movement and change exists at all. It simply attempts to establish
consistencies and relationships within the world of appearances. What may lie
behind this world is of little concern, and might be dismissed as ultimately
beyond our capacity to know, and it is fruitless for us to pursue such knowledge.
Or, it may be decided that there is nothing there for us to understand, and
that synthetic knowledge of this sort is not there to be had. Only analytical
and deductive insights have any meaning.
Rather than this being a straightforward opposite to synthetic thought
however, this analytical approach to reality does not utterly disdain all
aspects of synthesis. If consistency in law and precedent (in causes) are
pursued, this activity itself partakes of the notion that there are unchanging
and universal aspects of reality. The difference is that this pursuit of a
synthetic understanding of the world is confined purely to things which can be
observed and measured by us, and does not involve us in a hypothetical
understanding of things which cannot be directly observed and measured. This
view represents an unwillingness to go beyond what can be commonly understood,
to become involved in areas of thought and understanding which throw up
contradictory and paradoxical results, and much uncertainty. This view represents
a form of pragmatism, which would be likely to brand much speculative thought
as a waste of time, and which produces only profoundly unreal results.
A pragmatism of this sort is common to those studying ancient civilization
and ancient philosophy in our times. A synthetic understanding of ancient art,
sculpture, theology, ritual behaviour, religious liturgy, poetry, and
philosophy, is not sought, for a number of reasons, ranging from the notion that
a synthetic structure behind ancient social and intellectual thought and
practice is not there to be had at all, through to the suggestion that we
cannot understand it even if it is present, since it is dependent on esoteric
doctrine which is not available to us, and so we have to interpret the
materials as best we can, in a way which makes them as useful to us as
possible.
And so there is no real interest in ancient thought. The Neoplatonists have
been given a separate category of their own in the history of philosophy on
purely phenomenological and parochial grounds, though they did not understand
themselves as other than Platonists or Aristotelians. [5]
We can apparently therefore not learn much of use about Plato and Aristotle
from a study of their works, since they belonged to an essentially separate
tradition. Plato and Aristotle are endlessly examined for similarities and
difference in outlook and belief. But the purpose and meaning of many of their
works remain obscure. We can learn something of logic, epistemology, ontology,
ethics, moral thought, the relationships between things which are similar and
dissimilar, great and small, the ideas of justice, of virtue, of beauty, of the
nature of rulership, magnanimity, and of the nature of the divine to the
Greeks, and so on. These things are useful to us, as they have been over the
past two thousand years and more, even if some of the discussions are
distinctly unsatisfactory from our point of view. In other words, we approach ancient writings
on philosophy and theology in the same way we approach other aspects of ancient
civilization: out of the original context, and in a wholly inappropriate
alternative to that context, which addresses a modern academic agenda.
The idea of Being addressed here is the one which was endlessly discussed
in the ancient world, and was a central focus of the writings of Plato. When
Proclus was writing commentaries on Plato in the last days of the Platonic
Academy, he was writing about the same idea of Being, though the passage of
some nine hundred years changed some of the language, the metaphors and images
used, the frame of reference, and also allowed other related traditions into
the narrative. It is a mistake to look at both ends of the narrative as if they
were written on the same day, but it does not mean they have nothing useful to
say about each other.
[1] Of course the selection of the right data is not the
same at all periods for the same phenomena. A researcher seeking to support a
phenomenon within the frame of Newtonian mechanics would inevitably choose
different data to that chosen by a researcher framing the phenomenon within
Einsteinian mechanics. It is not a question of right and wrong data. The models
we bring to bear on a phenomenon determine the evidence which seems significant
to us.
[2] At the time of writing I read on an Ancient Near
Eastern mailing list an exchange about the language and grammar of the Quran,
between a western and an islamic scholar. The response of the latter to an
inference by the former was to say that if such a remark had been made by a
moslem he would have invited a stoning.
This is a very clear way of indicating that certain articulations of
thought are off-limits.
[3] From the introduction to The Art and
Architecture of the Ancient Orient, 1954
[4] Interestingly, though this is the basic form of
argument for Being, there is no common agreement about the implications and
consequences of this transcendent nature of the ultimate reality, and no
agreement that in fact it is one, and that it does not participate in the moving
image of reality. This lack of common agreement is extremely significant, and
the question will be returned to later in this work.
[5]
The works of Simplicius are almost entirely in the form of commentaries on
Aristotle. The texts are good enough for scholars to mine quotations from the
pre-Socratic philosophers, but not good enough to be reliable as a guide to
Aristotelian philosophy. The frame erected around the development of
pre-Socratic philosophy is a modern conjecture built on interpretation of these
quotations, supported by writings on the history of philosophy written in the
early centuries of the modern era.
No comments:
Post a Comment