The Excellence of the King
Throughout the texts and inscriptions and
iconography we are presented with images of the king as a kind of perfection.
He is at the apex of the social structure of Assyria and is its principal
priest (in terms of his participation in the key rituals). Thus he is the most
excellent of human beings and holds his position because of his theoretical
excellence in all aspects of Assyrian life: exercising the virtues of kingship,
justice, statecraft, warfare, divination, administration, etc.
It would be easy to argue that the king was
understood to have the privilege of contact with the divine on account of his
pre-eminence in human society; almost that the king arrogated this privilege to
himself on account of his power to do so. However this would be to retroject a
secularism into Assyrian society which the evidence does not warrant.
The office of priest, for example, is not
distinguished by a term which we can easily equate with "priest". The
kalu-priest is designated simply "kalu". In other words, the function
of these officials is not seen as apart from the function of the rest of the Assyrian
social structure: religion and society are inextricably intertwined, having
never been conceived as separate ways of looking at the world (Compare for
example the elaborate intertwining of everyday life and the understanding of
the structure of the world illustrated by Marcel Griaule's study of Dogon
belief: Conversations with Ogotemeli).
The term "apkallum" (used to describe Adapa's priesthood of Ea at
Eridu) was understood by the Assyrians to be a term indicating a mortal sage,
though in connection with Adapa I think the term to have a technical meaning.
In any case, there is little evidence that
people thought in antiquity this way up. Even if someone did steal privileges
by virtue of his power to do so, the act would be understood and explained
within a moral framework, and the success of the act would depend on the will
of the gods. When Esarhaddon entered Nineveh and sat on the throne of his
father, he describes how
"favourable
powers drew close in heaven and earth... messages of gods and goddesses they
sent me continuously and gave me courage"[Borger, R. Die Inschriften Asarhaddons (AfO Beiheft 9), 1959, Nin. A-F Ep. 2] (Translation
supplied by A.T.L. Kuhrt).
Instead, much of the evidence is explained
if we infer that the king understood that he owed his privileges of contact
with the gods and his rulership over mankind to his excellence and perfection.
In other words, that his wisdom and power came to him by virtue of his
perfection, not only in eminence among men, but among all men.
The king is described as "king of kings",
which concept may have been understood as essential to the function of his kingship,
and not merely as a vainglorious styling. From the Assyrian point of view, the
reason why there is a point of contact between the king and the gods at all is because
they have something in common, and that the point
of contact is precisely the pre-eminence, the excellence, and the perfection of
the king in all his roles. It is this commonality which establishes the
harmony between the world of man and that of the gods. Cf. Plato, Timaeus 31c-32c; also Aristotle, Politics 1277a, and Nicomachean Ethics Bk. X, chap. 8.
In antiquity in general, perfection is
understood as a kind of completion: the perfect is that which is complete, and
that which is complete is perfect. Thus the king is also complete, in his
attainments, his power, his wisdom and his capacity. In this the king emulates
the divine, all aspects of which must be complete in their own natures.
That completion was understood as a virtue
in itself is illustrated by the fact in Mesopotamia and elsewhere, sin was often
countered not by attempting to undo the sin directly, but by the perfect
performance of rituals and incantations. Each of these, properly performed,
counted towards the expiation of the sin, irrespective of the nature of the
sin. Thus, to undo the damage done by the sin, it is not necessary to repair
the damage, to make good the imperfection, directly (often impossible – see the
"Sin of Sargon" text in SAA
vol. IV, Starr): to undertake repair
without regard to context but complete attention to purpose is the requirement. See SLA
323 [= Harper 629], lines 13-17, which illustrates that completions in the
abstract are efficacious. Thus, in acting as "apkallum" (standing in
for the god Ea) in rituals necessary for the continuation of the Assyrian state
(as illustrated in the throne room relief where the king is shown apparently
engaged in the business of fertilizing the date palm represented as a sacred tree)
the ritual is brought closer to the divine creation, and the consonance of the
act with the divine will is emphasised.
The king was "chosen" by the gods
because of his special excellence and his virtue, and he was the person
responsible for performing very special actions. Everything associated with the
act being performed was of equal and critical importance: upon the timing of
the ritual depended its success - see SLA
342 [= Harper 406], where the auspicious day for a sacrifice is discussed; see also
SLA 344 [= Harper 365], and SLA 328 [= Harper 356]. Oaths were a
matter for auspicious days also, and the king was available to be visited likewise
only when the day was right - see SLA
341 [= Harper 384].
The king is the agent of the divine in the
fight against chaos and the maintenance of order in his realm (which struggle
might be characterized as war with the imperfect and the incomplete: compare
for example the "Enuma Elish" and the strange creatures which were
made in the first creation). Heidel The Babylonian Genesis. pp. 23-4 [Tablet I, lines 132-45]. See also pp. 75-81 for the surviving Greek accounts by Berossus
and Alexander Polyhistor. The struggle
against chaos is vividly illustrated in the palace reliefs according to the
metaphor of the battle between Marduk and Tiamat. The lion hunt sculptures from
the palace of Ashurbanipal echo this struggle. The king is also the final
judge, meaning that his insight into the true nature of matters is second to
none - see SLA 322 [= Harper 1006].
The divine is understood as some place on
the other side of the limit of the world which the king rules, from which he is
excluded except in terms of priestly contact.* SLA 327 [= Harper 565], which illustrates the fact that we are
excluded from the celestial world except via observation. He is near to the
divine, but not so proximate to qualify as divine himself. Though a letter suggests
that part of the aura of the king was the power to do exactly as he wished -
see SLA 324 [= Harper 137]. To those
lower down the social scale in Assyria this might count as divinity; but to those
able to juggle with the pattern of ideas within which Assyrian royalty
functioned, it would connote no more than proximity with the divine - see SLA 137 [= Harper 992].
As the most perfect individual in his state
the king nearly emulates the divine in containing all things: he is complete. The
completion of his nature and that of Assur can be made concrete by its literal realization. The king is "king of kings",
and this can be made real by conquest and the subjection of surrounding states
from the Upper Sea to the Lower Sea. Hence also his description as "king
of countries" and "king of the four quarters (lit., edges) of the
world".
It is possible that his
"official" moods were in imitation of the gods, understood to be manifest
in the motions of the planets: the Crown Prince was excluded from the presence
of the King when Mars was in opposition to the Sun and hence subject to
retrograde motions (which exclusion is an interesting reflection of the Adapa
myth,of central importance to Sargonid kingship: Ea knew that Adapa was not fit
to appear in the presence of Anu without some schooling in what to say) SLA 328 [= Harper 356]; see also SLA 342 [= Harper 356]; SLA
344 [= Harper 365]; SLA 345 [= Harper
652]. The same sort of equation was made between the geography of the
Mesopotamian world and the surface of the moon at the time of lunar eclipse –
see SLA 322 [= Harper 1006]. Roaf in
his Cultural Atlas of Mesopotamia
illustrates this letter, but gives no citation (22 May 678 B.C.). See also SLA 324 [= Harper 137]. See also
Parpola's Doctoral Thesis, Letters of Assyrian Scholars to Ashurbanipal and Esarhaddon
1971, Appendix 3B.
It is difficult to specify exactly what is
going on here, but it would appear that there is some kind of transactive
relationship understood to exist between the abstract (gods) and the concrete
(the earthly responsibilities of the king): the character of some of the acts
for which we have evidence is best explained by presuming that the principal
point of the acts was to create a harmony between heaven and earth; to act as agents, the viziers of the divine, not to supplant its position, or to exploit
it for personal ends. Prestige and propaganda are naturally of significance in
a world dominated by metaphors (the king being a metaphor for the divine), but
the state machine is driven by, both the internal logic of its theology, and the theology functioning as a tool
of state. In any case, the distinction between
the character of the state and the will of the gods has not yet been made.
The Assyrian concept of nobility
In Assyria justice was not based upon
equity, but upon who you were. Thus, the kind of treatment one might expect
depended upon what kind of position one occupied in the social structure. In other
words the arrangement of society was hierarchical, and the honour and moral
worth of an individual depended upon his social position (which, given the
complexity of the court and society, might not be reflected by means of the
possession of a title). Hence the poor and the helpless by definition were
morally worthless, deserving pity; and the rich and the powerful, also by
definition, were naturally of high moral character SLA 329 [= Harper 1237], which illustrates that only the divine can
exist in harmony. Thus, the more noble the individual (reflected by social position),
the greater the proximity to the divine.
The basis of such a social system is
teleological: each social position being understood as a rung on the ladder
with the divine at the very top; the king stood in close proximity to the divine.
The divinity represented a perfect completion, each social position being a
more or less imperfect emulation (though perhaps achieving its own special
completion of no significant worth). It would seem however that sometimes the
hierarchical order could be reversed, for reasons which are difficult to understand:
see SLA 329 [= Harper 1237].â Since
completion and perfection were the criteria by which the excellence of acts,
things and people were judged, fact and value interpenetrate. Everything in
such a world speaks of its meaning.
This of course means that the moral
structure of the Assyrian state ought to be intelligible, at least to some
extent, in terms of Aristotle's understanding of the way human beings ought to function,
since in both the Politics and the Ethics he discusses actions and
structures in terms of honour and
completion. Herodotus too constructed his Histories
on the basis of a teleological model, interestingly associating space and direction
with moral qualities [see also Aristotle, Politics
1327b-1328a].
Both of these writers lived some time after
the fall of the Neo-Assyrian Empire, which means that caution is important.
Herodotus however lived close enough in time to at least contemplate writing a
history of Assyria. Though Greek and Assyrian cultures are clearly quite different
entities, a comparison between the two might shed considerable light on the
latter.
The King and Totality
The concept of totality as a feature of
both the Adapa (myth and discipline) and Assyrian theology, arises as the
logical corollary of the association of the king with perfection, and thus
completion: it is another way of framing the idea that the universe is
structured according to degrees of participation in the ultimate completion
(the realm of the divine). This ultimate completion is transcendent, in that we
can have no commerce with it except via individuals with a special quality in
common (temporary or permanent). However, the essential characteristic of the
divine, if it cannot exist in the world, can be emulated within the limitations
imposed by the nature of earthly reality. Hence we find the king engaged in
conquest and empire building, attempting to take hold of the known universe and
to subject it to his will (which is naturally the will of the divine). This ambition
(if not necessarily the reality) is reflected in the style of the king’s
inscriptions, whether addressed to a human or divine audience. Client kings
make sense within this emulatory system: he need not rule directly, just as Marduk
need not. A proxy representative (bound by oaths to the Assyrian king, justas
the king is bound by oath to the god) is not only satisfactory, but fits
harmoniously into the Assyrian model of the world.
Aristotle was insistent that, while a man
might be regarded as a god among men, a man could not be divine while still living,
because the divine has a strict definition. Man is connected with the divine in
a participatory sense through the accomplishment of ends and completion. While
man has existence on earth he cannot be truly divine (though he might be truly human
only by virtue of something of the divine within him).
That Aristotle's definition of the divine
is traditional is supported by the fact that no clear evidence exists for the paying
of divine honours to a Greek (while still alive) before and including Alexander
the Great (Heroic honours being a quite different matter: the different species
of honours require to be clearly distinguished).
That the teleological world view was important
in the fourth century B.C. is illustrated vividly by the proskynesis debate at the
Persian court of Alexander. The best account is by Arrian, and it presents the
debate as a struggle between theteleological view of divinity (of which he must
have been aware, having been Aristotle's pupil) and the Democritean view of theological
matters (in which nothing happens according to fortune, for there is nothing
beyond the meaningless concourse of atoms). The debate is a miniature of the
struggle between Plato's Gods and Giants (the Sophist): ironically Anaxarchus
tempted Alexander to side with the giants in order that he be regarded as a
god. Thus it is a fourth century miniature of the struggle between the ancient
teleology (in which actual divinity is incompatible with complete physical
existence), and the moderns (who restrict themselves to dealing with the idea
that divinity is a metaphor, with only the meaning with which it is invested by
its devotees).
No comments:
Post a Comment