[This is an extract from 'Hume and Kant on Reality', a chapter in The Sacred History of Being, published November 2, 2015]
Kant defines metaphysics very closely as something whose ‘fundamental
propositions … and its fundamental concepts must never be taken
from experience’, since metaphysical knowledge lies beyond experience. The
ground of metaphysics will not be either ‘outer experience’, which he defines
as the source of physics, nor ‘inner experience, which provides the basis for
empirical psychology.’ In other words metaphysics is a priori knowledge,
‘out of pure understanding and pure reason’.
Kant recognizes the need to differentiate metaphysics from pure
mathematics, and refers the reader to the Critique, where he says
‘Philosophical cognition is rational cognition from concepts. Mathematical cognition is rational
cognition from the construction of
concepts.’ [i]
He expands on this by saying that ‘to construct a concept means to exhibit a
priori the intuition corresponding to it. Hence construction of a concept
requires a non-empirical intuition. Consequently this intuition, as intuition,
is an individual object; but as the construction of a concept, (a universal
presentation), it must nonetheless express in the presentation its universal
validity for all possible intuitions falling under the same concept.’
Kant uses the example of the construction of a triangle, arguing that this
construction exhibits the object which corresponds to this concept ‘either
through imagination alone, or in pure intuition.’ It can be drawn on paper of
course, as a mathematical figure, but in such a case the representation is an
empirical intuition, not a pure intuition, though both in the case of the pure intuition
and the empirical intuition, Kant has exhibited the object a priori,
without having used a model taken from experience (meaning that only the
properties of a triangle have been used in its construction). Though the drawn
figure is empirical, yet it serves to express the concept ‘without impairing
the concept’s universality’. Only those
properties which it is necessary to consider for the construction of the
triangle are involved – the many inconsequential details of a physical triangle
– the length of the sides, and the angles of the triangle, are not involved in
the abstraction. All such irrelevant details are removed from the concept, and
the result is therefore wholly abstracted from any particular instance of a
triangle.
Kant’s argument is therefore that ‘philosophical cognition contemplates the
particular only in the universal’. By contrast, he says that mathematical
cognition ‘contemplates the universal in particular, and indeed even in the
individual’. This might seem at first sight to be a strange distinction,
however Kant explains himself clearly, saying that even in the case of this
mathematical cognition, the contemplation of it is ‘a priori, and by
means of reason.’ And so, ‘just as this individual is determined under certain
universal conditions of construction, so the object of the concept – to which
this individual corresponds only as its schema – must be thought of as
determined universally. Thus the
essential difference between these two kinds of rational cognition ‘consists in
this difference of form, and does not rest on the difference of their matter or
objects.’
[End of extract]
No comments:
Post a Comment